[revised October 2020]

Reading notes to accompany Aristotle readings

Michael Taber, Department of Philosophy

St. Mary’s College of Maryland, USA

 

These are helps for reading Aristotle as excerpted in Irwin & Fine’s Aristotle: Introductory Readings by Hackett Publishing, followed with some supplements I’ve added outside of their selections. I have omitted from these pages notes about the works in Irwin & Fine that I usually skip when I teach Aristotle (e.g., De Interpretatione, Posterior Analytics, Topics).

For some of the sections that we skip in class, I’ve included notes below, but have them right-justified (aligned with the right-hand margin) so that it’s clear to my students which sections they can skip for the purposes of our class.

 

Physics

(Ta Phusika, Growing Things)

Book I.1 

Here Aristotle is laying out his basic goal and methodology.  Worth noting, and perhaps surprising, is his claim that our understanding should “advance from universals to particulars”; he’s not working with an image like the Allegory of the Cave, which would involve a move from particulars to universals.

 

Book I.7-8 [Remember: right-justified; therefore, skippable for class]

Aristotle is concerned here with the phenomenon of “coming to be” (or, equivalently, “coming into being” or simply “becoming”).  He thinks that it is in principle a different kind of change from change of quality (alteration), change of quantity (growth), or change of location (movement).  These last three kinds of change have a subject—that is, something that undergoes the alteration, growth, or movement.  But either coming into being does not have anything that moves from non-being into being or if there is a subject, it is a different kind of subject from that involved in the other kinds of changes.

 

 

Book II.1 

[N.B.: Dr. Cynthia Freeland’s brief guide to Bk. II might of assistance: http://www.uh.edu/~cfreelan/courses/PhysII.html]

Some points to reflect on include his way of distinguishing between natural objects and artifacts.   The main point of this chapter is to show that there is a reason to think that the nature (phusis) of a thing is more the matter of the thing (see the passage 193a15-31; be able to put in your own words what this reason is) and to show that there are also reasons to think that the nature of a thing is more the shape/form of a thing.  In fact, he gives three such reasons, so see if you can isolate them.  (Hint: he gives all three in the paragraph 193b7-18.  The first two such sentences give the first reason, and summarize the previous paragraph.  The second and third reasons are each introduced by “Further....”)

 

Book II.2 

Notice Aristotle’s discussion of how the student of nature studies things like snub (like the how the snub-nose of some breeds of dog came to be, or how it affects their respiration), not things like curved (even though a snub nose is a curved nose).  Natural objects are, Aristotle holds, “less separable” than mathematical objects.  (Snubness is less separable than curved, because snub = curved + nose, so snubness is, in a sense, embedded in nose.) So when the student of nature studies, say, the straightness of the growth of a certain species of tree, the student is not studying straightness in itself, the way a geometer would.  And since the Platonists (“those who say there are Ideas”) separate (Aristotle claims) the Forms from the physical world they are trying to account for, they are in principle unable to account for the physical world.  (Aristotle would presumably say that the best they could do would be to account for the mathematical world.)

 

Book II.3 

This is a major site for what’s come to be called Aristotle’s doctrine of the four causes: the material cause (the out of which), the formal cause (the by which), the efficient (or making) cause (the from which), and the final cause (the for the sake of which).  Get clear on the examples he gives of each.

After laying out his doctrine of the four causes, which is mostly clear, he raises the idea of a “coincident cause,” which discussion mostly isn’t. 

I think what he’s getting at includes the phenomenon whereby, if I stumble on a loose brick on the path, the next issue of The Point News might read “Philosopher Trips While Walking.” While there would be nothing false about this headline, my being a philosopher would be merely coincident to my unfortunate brick encounter.  (Unless, of course, I’d been reading, say, about Thales while walking; then one could make the case that “being a philosopher” was more than a coincident cause of the fall!)

 

Book II.4 & 5

In these chapters Aristotle sets out to obtain some clarity about in what sense luck and chance can be said to be causes.

 

Book II.6

This chapter continues the discussion of luck and chance, and includes an account of what distinguishes chance from luck.

 

Book II.7

Here Aristotle sums up his discussion of causation, and singles out the issue of the two sorts of initiators of motion.  Later, he’ll call these unmoved movers and moved movers.

 

Book II.8

Aristotle distinguishes between what has come to be called teleological explanation (like it rains because it’s better that way, or because Zeus wills it) and mechanistic explanation (the necessity of how evaporation/condensation/precipitation works). His making this distinction explicit is immensely important for the subsequent history of philosophy.

Delightful is that Aristotle entertains natural selection (in the version that had been advocated by Empedocles), and gives what amounts to an argument against it.

 

Book II.9

Since Aristotle wants to say that necessity plays a causal role in change, and since he has given his doctrine of causation, he realizes that he has to find a home for necessity in his view of causation.  This requires some stretching and pulling.

 

Book VI.9

Aristotle discusses Zeno’s four paradoxes of motion: the Dichotomy, the Achilles, the arrow, and the stadium.  His solution to the second depends on his solution to the first, which he says has been discussed earlier. This earlier discussion is not included in this edition of passages, however; but be patient, for in VIII.8 the editors include another passage in which Aristotle offers a solution of the Dichotomy.

 

 

Book  VIII.5

Aristotle holds that all motion requires a mover and a moved, and sometimes the same entity can be both.  If I use a stick and bat a ball, then the ball is the moved and the stick is the mover.  But since the stick moves only because the stick was moved by my hand, then the stick is a moved mover.  In order to avoid an infinite regress, however, Aristotle thinks there must at some point in the process be a first mover, which is also called a self-mover or an unmoved mover. 

 

Book VIII.6

Here Aristotle takes up the issue of whether the unmoved movers are everlasting (he argues in the affirmative), and whether it makes sense to posit that there are more than one (he argues in the negative, and notice how his argument invokes something like the principle of parsimony, otherwise known as Ockham’s [also spelled “Occam’s”] Razor).

 

Book VIII.8

See the entry for VI.9.

 

 

Generation and Corruption

(Peri Geneseōs kai Phthoras, Coming to Be and Passing Away)

 

The Physics is about change (about what causes it, about coincidental change, etc.), and G&C focuses on a specific type of change: coming into being and passing away. Other types of change, like change of quantity (getting bigger or smaller), change of place (locomotion), or change of quality (alteration, like becoming sleepy) have a subject of change—that is, something that undergoes the change.

But this seems (where does Aristotle come down on this seeming?) not to hold for something’s coming into being or passing away.

Aristotle is on his game to devote some time to thinking about this.

 

Book I

Chapter 5

Test yourself: can you explain what Aristotle’s point is in saying, “a dead body would more readily seem to have flesh and bone than to have a hand or an arm”? If/when you get to the point of understanding this, you’ll earn your bronze-level Aristotle merit badge.

 

Book II

Chapter 3

Note how Aristotle says that the elements are not foundational. Rather, they are complexes.

 

Chapter 5

In this chapter Aristotle talks about there being “some other matter common to them” [i.e., common to the elements], which sounds like what later commentators will call “prime matter.”

 

 

De Anima

(Peri Psychēs, On the Soul)

Book I

Chapter 1

            Notice how from the start, Aristotle assumes the existence of the psyche.  He does not list as one of the questions to be examined whether there is such a thing.  If we were to raise this to him, his response, like that of anyone in his day, would likely be, “But surely a living organism differs from a dead one.”

 

402a1-9

Aristotle distinguishes between attributes of the psyche and attributes of the animal that has the psyche.  Can you think of clear cases of the one, clear cases of the other, and unclear cases?

 

 

403a3-b21

            The remainder of the chapter gives us the first clues about what Aristotle takes to be the issues involved in whether such things as emotions (he focuses on the example of anger) involve only the body or the psyche too, and the related issue of whether the psyche is separable from matter.  Take good notes on your careful reading, for you will find yourselves later referring back to this section.

 

403a24-b9

            Note Aristotle’s description of a thoroughly materialist account of anger (as the boiling of the blood) and his “dialectical” account (as the desire for retaliation).  Note how he uses this passage to argue that because the study of the psyche involves the study of material things, the study of the psyche falls within the province of the study of nature.  We are witnessing the birth of naturalistic psychology.

 

Book II

Chapter 1

This chapter contains some general comments about what a psyche is.

412a6-21
The psyche isn't substance in the fullest sense of substance (ousia), namely in the sense in which the bronze sphere is substance. Instead it actualizes matter into a composite, and it's that composite which is substance in the fullest sense.

412a22-27
Aristotle distinguishes between the first and the second actuality of something. What he means is this. Let Alice be ignorant of (but capable of learning about), say, the cause of the winds. Let Betty know the cause of the winds but not be thinking about it now (as she is asleep). And let Cathy know the cause of the winds and be presently explaining the matter to Daphne. Betty has actualized what Alice has as mere potential, yet Cathy is actualizing something which Betty both has actually (in that she actually possesses the knowledge) and has potentially (in that she's not, in her sleep, actualizing that knowledge). So Cathy has actualized her knowledge in two senses, whereas Betty has only the first actualization.

Aristotle's claim here is that psyche is the first actualization. Why is this point worth him making? Well, for starters, the implication of saying that psyche is the first actualization is that the psyche would be not some sort of activity, but the capacity to engage in some sorts of activities; more precisely, not the undeveloped capacity (that would be Alice), but the actualized potential to engage in some sort of activities.

At some point, then, Aristotle will have to tell us which are the relevant activities. He starts on this project at the passage 412b10-413a10, where he says that the psyche of something is the what-it-is-to-be-that-thing, by which he means something like the essential function (the ergon, "peculiar work") of the thing. This, of course, leaves unaddressed the question of which particular activities constitute the psyche of which living things (that is, which particular activities constitute the peculiar workings of which living things). This question will start to be addressed in II.2.

It also leaves open how the psyche actualizes the body; for example, does the psyche actualize the body like the way a sailor sails a ship? If not, then how else? This will come in (the notoriously perplexing) III.5.

412b3-9
What does Aristotle mean by his response to the question "Are the psyche and body one?"

Chapter 2

413b22
Aristotle’s word phantasia is translated by Fine and Irwin (in editions from Hackett Publishing Company) as "appearance" (and see their glossary entry for this term), and by Hamlyn (in Ackrill’s A New Aristotle Reader) as "imagination." It is a difficult word to translate, for it is more interesting than "appearance" but less fancy than what we mean by "imagination." When Aristotle talks of phantasia, he means it not in the sense of what distinguishes poets from mental drudges like the rest of us. He means it in the traditional sense, used even by Descartes, to refer to something like "the ability for at least part of the outside world to appear to you to be a certain way." Something like "the ability to entertain images." So in this sense, Aristotle thinks that a fish must have phantasia, for it must have an image (provided by sense-perception) of the food source towards which it's moving.

413b25-32
Aristotle proceeds to mess up his nice picture by declaring that thought alone is separable (from the body). Furthermore, this seems to land him in the Platonist camp, for it represents a case of a form (the psychic faculty of thought) as being able to exist separately from the world of spatio-temporal particulars. Either Aristotle is right that there is something essentially different about thought (as distinguished from self-feeding, growth, movement, and sensation), or we have to chalk this exception up to Aristotle not being able to throw off the influence of his teacher.

For what it's worth, we can see a similar problem in Aristotle's discussion from Met. XII.5, 6 & 9, where he talks about the divine substance. Here again there is a form which can exist separate from spatio-temporal particulars, and so perhaps represents another bit of residual Platonism.

But then maybe it's the same bit. For what is it that Aristotle takes the divine substance to be doing? Thinking. Which is exactly the exception he's making here at 413b25-32.

Chapter 3

Aristotle gets back into his Aristotelian mode when he says that not much can be said about psyche in general, and that to understand what a psyche is we need to study different sorts of empsyched beings. This approach is what makes Aristotle's mind so well-suited for studying, nay starting, biology.

 

Chapter 4

This chapter explores the most basic psyche, the nutritive psyche.

 

415a26-b1
Note Aristotle's teleology in claiming that everything living reproduces so as to partake of the everlasting as much as possible. He looks around, notices that all forms of life reproduce, and concludes that there must be a universal "urge" (whether felt or unfelt) to reproduce. He does not settle on (or entertain) the more mechanistic explanation that forms of life which don't reproduce die off and so aren't around to be noticed by Aristotle.

415b9-28
Aristotle claims that the psyche is the cause of the body in three ways: it's the efficient cause (the "from which"), the final cause (the "for the sake of which"), and the formal cause (the "by which," here described as "the substance" of the body). Obviously, the psyche can't be the material cause (the "out of which") of the body.

416a6
What does he mean by saying "in accordance with their functions, a plant’s roots correspond to an animal’s head"?

416a9-18
Now that Aristotle has claimed that it's the psyche that is responsible for the ability of a living thing to feed itself and grow, he must counter the view that it's fire that is the essence of feeding and growth. Why might someone think that fire is the source of feeding and growth? Well, fire is, after all, the only element which increases by itself. Effort must be taken to ensure that a fire doesn't feed itself, for except in artificial conditions (like sand pits and wood stoves), fire left on its own will spread. That's fire's nature. The nature of composite things ("everything naturally constituted") involves proportion and limit (note the echo of Pythagoras here), and so an incomposite element like fire isn't up to the job of limiting feeding. Aristotle perhaps is thinking that if there were fire in us which allows us to feed and grow, then that fire would grow out of control, and so consume our very bodies. Interesting.

Chapter 5

This chapter discusses the psyches which have the faculty of perception.

 

417a2-418a7
Spread your fingers out. If it's the job of skin to perceive touch, then why can't you feel your fingers' skin?

Look hard. If your retina is the organ of sight, then why can't you see your retina? Or your optic nerve? Or firings in your optic cortex?

What does your tongue taste like, your nose smell like?

What do your ears sound like? Why do you hear a bell and not the fluttering of your eardrums? (If you say, "But they're the same thing; the bell is the fluttering of the eardrum," then consider how a bell can be two hundred years old without the fluttering of an eardrum being so aged. If you more carefully say, "Well, the sound of the bell is the fluttering of the eardrum," then consider that [i] you've taken the world away from us, for we no longer hear bells, see people, taste chocolate, but we hear middle-C, see colors, taste sweetness. The world of objects has been replaced by a flood of sensations. Further consider that [ii] if the sound of the bell is identical with the fluttering of the eardrum, then the bell makes no sound if there is no eardrum around to flutter.)

What is Aristotle's answer to "why we do not perceive the senses themselves"? (This chapter isn't Aristotle at his clearest, but it has something to do with the actual/potential distinction.)

418a4-26
Aristotle’s distinction between the proper objects of perceptions and the common objects came to be influential to those coming later.

Chapter 6
This chapter presents Aristotle’s account of what the object of percep­tion is.  He claims that each sense has a “proper object” (which no other sense can sense; and for those in the market for certainty, these we can be certain of); that there are common objects which can be perceived incidental to perceiving the  proper objects; and that I see the son of Diares only coinci­dentally (not coincidental by virtue of the son of Diares being a common object, but by virtue of him being coincidentally related to the white patch I see from a distance).

A further question, but one not taken up by Aristotle until III.2 (not included in this edition), is exactly which relation is denoted by this “related to.”  Despite Aristotle’s use of the verb “to be” (“if the white thing were the son of Diares”), the relation can’t be the relation of identity; for then what’s true of the one is true of the other, and so since I see the whiteness more than incidentally, I’d have to see the son of Diares more than incidentally.  This is the intriguing question “If what we see isn’t things in the world, then just what is the relationship between what we see and the world?”  George Berkeley (1685‑1753) answers the question most creatively by denying that there is a world; he claims (and argues for the claim) that all that exists (not just all that we can have access to) is perceptions (or minds in which those perceptions inhere). 

 

Chapter 11

This chapter gives Aristotle's account of the sense of touch, and how it differs and doesn't differ from the other senses.

 

Chapter 12

This chapter draws a lesson about form and matter from the rest of the book. It is an important lesson too, for he uses it in his discussion of thinking in III.4.

 

424a18-28
Aristotle concludes his discussion of perception by claiming that sensing is the reception of the form of the sensed object without its matter. That the matter isn't communicated can be seen in two ways. First (and this is a point Aristotle doesn't make here), sensing an apple doesn't affect the matter of the apple (and affects the form only in the sense of making that form shared by my perceptual faculty), and certainly doesn't put the whole material apple into my perceptual faculty. Second (and this is left implicit from Aristotle's interest in all sensation requiring a medium), the medium of each instance of sensation acts as a blanket or filter which allows the form but not the matter of the object into my perceptual faculty.

424a33-b19
Aristotle ends his conclusion by distinguishing the perceptual psyche from the first species of psyche which he had discussed, the nutritive psyche, which is had by plants. The nutritive psyche has to be able to be affected by the matter of objects.

To his credit, Aristotle doesn't stop there. He entertains the question "How can something be affected by a perceptual quality (e.g., a smell) without that thing perceiving that quality?" It is a good question, but smell isn't the clearest example he could have used. He uses later the better case of light and darkness. Light and darkness are visual qualities, yet they can affect plants; does that mean that plants must be able to see? This question is especially poignant because of Aristotle's emphasis on the sensory medium; since light and darkness don't directly affect the body, but only the sensory medium (air or water), how can that sensory medium in turn affect, say, a plant unless the plant can see? In other words, if sensing is being affected by a change in a sensory medium, then plants would have to see.

He points out the exception for touch and taste (424b13). What is touched or tasted directly affects a sensory medium, but this sensory medium is the body (the skin or the tongue). So tangible qualities, like hot and cold, can affect plants without the plants being able to sense them. When a heated iron touches a plant, it affects the plant by the matter of the iron burning the matter of the plant; form is not sufficient, so this can't be a case of perception.

But this doesn't allow us to explain the case of light and darkness affecting the plant, for there the matter of the source of light need not touch the matter of the plant.

Aristotle doesn't resolve this, and the end of the chapter "looks like a number of lecturer's questions thrown out seriatim by way of challenge" (D. W. Hamlyn, Aristotle's De Anima, Books II and III, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968, p.115). But he does suggest in one of his questions that there is something more to sensing than being affected by a perceptual quality. This is a weighty issue, for it involves such questions as "Where in the processing of the visual system does the seeing happen? If in the brain, then in a particular neuron?" and "What exactly happens in the brain of one who understands an explanation of the Pythagorean theorem that doesn't happen in the brain of one who doesn't understand but who nonetheless perceives the words and pictures?" This last goes beyond perception into cognition; the plant is to the perceiver as the mere perceiver is to the knower. This takes us to Book III, where Aristotle takes up the thinking psyche.

Book III

Chapter 3

Aristotle here discusses what phantasia is, and how it differs from perception, belief, and knowledge. This serves as a bridge between his discussions of perception and of thinking.
Irwin & Fine render phantasia as “appearance,” and others (like Hamlyn) translate it as “imagination” (not in the specific sense of creativity, but in the sense of “imaging” or “forming an image of something).

428a6-17
He adduces four different considerations for why perceiving differs from imaging (which is an appropriately less ambitious word than "imagining"; to image something is for you to have that thing appear to you): at "For perception is...," at "Moreover,...," at "Further,...," and at Again,...." What are the four? Laurels to those getting the fourth (in a way that makes it genuinely different from the rest).

It’s not clear why, but the final sentence repeats the first of the four points.

428a18-24
He gives a reason for phantasia not being knowledge, and two reasons for it not being belief.

428a25-b9
He gives an argument for phantasia not being a combination of belief and perception. The last part (b5-9) of the passage is difficult, but makes sense.

Chapter 4

Now we get squarely to Aristotle's views on the nature of the thinking faculty (intellect, nous).

429a14-18
Although Aristotle seems only to suppose that perception is analogous to thought, he seems go further and to endorse the analogy, at least insofar as thinking requires that the intellect be capable of receiving the form of the object of thought. The analog is said of perception at the opening of II.12.

429a19-29
This passage is not only crucial for Aristotle's account of the psyche, but the point it makes is hugely influential in the history of theorizing about the mind, its relation to the brain, and its ability to attain knowledge.

Aristotle holds that because everything can come to be known by the cognitive psyche (nothing in the cosmos need remain locked away from us), the intellect must have no nature. It is pure potentiality. For if the intellect had an actual nature, a form of its own, that nature would interrupt the ability of the intellect to receive the forms of some objects. The slate has to be blank (actually blank, though potentially full; cf. 430a1) in order for everything to be legibly written on it.

It won't be until Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781 and 1787) that someone proposes in any detail that the mind is hardwired to think with certain categories (like space, time, causality, substance), with the consequence that anything not conforming to those categories couldn't be an object of thought for us. Aristotle is more optimistic about the ability of the intellect to know everything in principle.

But that's not all. Aristotle draws out the implication that if the intellect is to be characterless so as to be able to take on the character of anything it thinks about, then it cannot "be mixed with the body." This is reminiscent of 413b24-31, where he had said that the intellect alone is separable (from the body? from the organism, including the rest of the psyche?).

Despite this precedent, this poses no small problem for Aristotle's general account of the psyche in II.1: "The psyche must, then, be substance qua form of a natural body which has life potentially...The psyche, therefore, will be the actuality of a body of this kind." If the psyche is form and actuality, then how can the intellect (part of the psyche, after all) be formless and pure potentiality?

Second, even if Aristotle adjusts his general account of what a psyche is, then, given his association of matter with potentiality and form with actuality (412a9), it stands to reason that if the intellect is without form, it's without actuality. But then if it's potentiality, wouldn't it have to be material?

Third, Aristotle believes that even matter has a form, though a lower level form than that of which the matter is matter. For example, a lump of bronze has the form of being a certain ratio of the four elements, even before the sculptor induces the higher level form of sphericality onto the lump. Since matter has some form, that limits the potential it has. Bronze could never become food, for instance. And even the element of water could never become fire. But even if Aristotle responds to the second point above with the claim that the intellect is purer potentiality then anything material could ever be, wouldn't it follow that when the intellect isn't thinking, it vanishes into the void (since it has no nature of its own)? To call this counter-intuitive would be too gentle.

429a29-b9
Aristotle notes two ways in which perception differs from thought, and they both involve perception being, and thought not being, separate from the body. (1) Only thought isn't worsened by having an intense object. (2) The intellect can think by itself, but the perceptual faculties require an external object. (And lest you object that it's possible to imagine an object that's not present, remember that Aristotle has already given not one, but four reasons for holding that imaging is distinct from perception [428a5-16].)

429b23-430a9
Aristotle poses and responds to two questions about his view of what the intellect is. (1) If x can act on y only in virtue of some similarity between them (for example, rain can act on a seed only if they are both material objects and only if they exist at the same time and place), then how can actual objects of thought act on a completely non-actual intellect? (2) Can the intellect think about itself? (Given what Aristotle has said in this chapter, why might this second question be a special challenge for him?)

He provides an answer to each in the second half of the passage. What are his answers?

Chapter 5

This is where Aristotle introduces the distinction between the passive intellect and the active (or producing) intellect. It represents a fast break from the previous chapter's analogy between perception and thought (cf. 429a14-18). In fact, it is surprising that the account of thinking in III.4 is so bereft of any hint of there being two intellects, or, at the very least, two aspects of the intellect. An example of this puzzlement is that where before he had said that the intellect has no nature and is only potential (429a21), he now commits himself to saying that there is an intellect which is pure activity, and so is pure form and has a full nature (activity, form, and nature all being linked in Aristotle's metaphysics). This new wrinkle can't simply be appended onto III.4, for it's incompatible with much of III.4.

Any ideas?

Chapters 10 & 11

These chapters discuss how thinking things get going. Desire is necessary but not sufficient for deliberation about what to do. You’re on your own for the rest of these short chapters.

 

Categories

(Katēgoriai, Predications)

[This is the first set of excerpts in Fine & Irwin. We’re skipping this work.]

Chapter 1

In this chapter, Aristotle is warning of us some of the subtle ways in which language can confuse us.  Two things can share the same name without sharing the same nature. 

While it’s true to say “That’s an animal” while pointing at a man or at a painting of an ox, they’re animals in different ways.  Strictly speaking the painting of an ox isn’t an animal; it’s a painting of an animal.  But it’s still an animal in a way, for we get on quite fine stopping to look at the painting, and asking someone “Can you find the animal in this painting?”  We’d be rather taken aback at a reply along the lines of “Harrumph, there’s no animal there.  Just a painting of one!”

This first way of two things having the same name without sharing the same thing nature is the way in which a man and a painted ox are both animals—they are said to be animals homonymously.  (“Homonym” means “same name”.... as in “the same ONLY in name.”)

The second way of two things sharing a name but not a nature is what Aristotle calls being called synonymously the same thing, the way that it’s true of both a man and an ox to say “That’s an animal.”  What it is for a man to be an animal is exactly what it is for an ox to be an animal, insofar as the definition, or essence, of animal will be the same in both claims.  But a man is obviously very different from an ox.  So “animal” in “The man is an animal” and “animal” in “The ox is an animal” are synonyms; the occurrences of the word have the same meaning, even though the man and the ox aren’t the same kind of thing.  They share a predicate (being an animal) but not a full nature.

The third way can be made clearer by taking a liberty with Aristotle’s examples, and very compressed discussion.  The name “grammar” can apply to a body of knowledge (about the way parts of speech work) or to a physical book (“Can I buy this grammar from you?”).  Same name, but very different entities; only one can be purchased, for instance.  Since we’re not playing fast and loose with the name, in the sense of equivocating, they’re not grammars homonymously.  Yet they’re also not grammars in the same way—or synonymously.  Rather one gets its name from the other; the book gets to be called a grammar because of its content—it’s about grammar. So the subject and the book have the same name (that is, they’re both grammars) because they’re named paronymously; think of it meaning that they’re named derivatively.  And the derivation continues further, for the grammarian gets that name because he or she studies grammar.

The word “brave” can name both the equivalent of being courageous and a Native American adult male.  These two are not the same, for we don’t call the young Lakota man “a courageous,” even if we think he is courageous. The courageous action and the Lakota youth are named brave paronymously, because the latter derives his name from the former.  Same name, different nature, but related natures.  Where synonymy is like two parallel tracks equal to each other (a man is an animal and an ox is an animal in parallel ways), paronymy is like tracks diverging from a hub (a grammarian and a grammar and the quality of being grammatical all get their names by radiating from the knowledge of parts of speech, which is the central variety of grammar.

 

 

Chapter 2

As you read this chapter, fill in this matrix:

 

 

said of a subject

not said of a subject

in a subject

 

 

not in a subject

 

 

 

Dr. Cynthia Freeland’s cat may be of service for this chapter and the next: http://www.uh.edu/~cfreelan/courses/categories.html 

 

Chapter 3

A straightforward enough discussion of what we might call the transitivity of predication.

 

Chapter 4

This list of ten categories is often referred to as Aristotle’s doctrine of the categories. 

 

Chapter 5

A much longer chapter than the preceding, its opening sentence reveals how Aristotle is using chapters 2 and 4, with chapters 1 and 3 being used later in chapter 5.  Think of chapter 5, therefore, as the for-the-sake-of-which for the preceding chapters. 

Aristotle here lays out in this chapter what he takes to be distinctive of primary being (= primary substance), as opposed to secondary being (which includes what he here calls secondary substance, as well as all the other nine categories).  So white, or whiteness, and man or humanness or humanity, exist; not in the primary sense in which Plato thought, however, but in a secondary sense. What primarily exists is this man or that man, of whom whiteness is or is not predicated (or said) or in whom this particular whiteness inheres or is in.

 

 

 

 

Metaphysics

(Ta Meta Ta Phusika, After the Physics)

 

Book I.1 

Note how Aristotle “builds” knowledge, and builds it in a way that is distinctively more empirically oriented than Plato (as seen in Plato’s Analogy of the Sun, Divided Line, or Allegory of the Cave).

The desire to understand, however, doesn’t have to be built at all, according to Aristotle’s opening sentence.  Someone who isn’t interested in figuring out the environment would be a defective human.

 

Book I.2

The sense of “science” (epistēmē, as described in Irwin & Fine’s glossary) that Aristotle means here is not as narrow as what we mean by the word.  He means by it no more than a systematic discipline of knowledge.  (See reading notes for IV.1 below for more.)

Philosophy begins in wonder.  Beautiful.

 

Book I.3-4

            A review of some Presocratics.  These names should now be familiar to you, and you can use these chapters as something of a review that Aristotle has written for your final exam.

 

Book I.6 & 9 

Here Aristotle describes some criticisms of Plato’s Theory of Forms (to which he usually refers as Plato’s Theory of Ideas; he does use the word idea in the Greek, but idea no more means our “idea” than apologia in the Greek means our “apology”).

The final paragraph of ch. 9 closes with a condensed (and therefore frustratingly dense) three arguments that Platonists give for the existence of the Forms (argument from the sciences, the one over the many, the argument about thinking), and mentions “the Third Man,” which is an objection to Plato’s Forms.

 

 

Book IV.1

Recall the note from Metaphysics I.2 above. 

There is knowledge of the capitals of all 50 states, but this knowledge doesn’t qualify as epistēmē.  (Such knowledge would qualify as what Irwin & Fine subscript as knowledgeg or knowledgeo, but not knowledgee, which is the variety that is etymologically related to epistēmē.)

An epistēmē is also not just a systematic discipline of study, for then astrology would qualify as epistēmē.  (After all, people can spend years studying how the alignment of certain planets and stars is supposed to influence events here on earth—where the influence is claimed to transcend mere gravity and light transmission.) 

An epistēmē, properly defined is a systematic discipline of knowledge.  Yet it would be stylistically ugly to translate every occurrence of the word epistēmē with “systematic discipline of knowledge,” so most translators simply opt for “knowledge” (usually with a footnote somewhere that epistēmē is more specific than our “knowledge”—due to the case of the state capitals above) or opt for “science” (usually with a footnote that epistēmē is more general than our very narrow sense of “science”). 

History is an epistēmē, but most of us wouldn’t consider it a science.

            So the take-home message here is that although Irwin & Fine use “science” as their translation for epistēmē, don’t think of it as science in a narrow sense.

            Aristotle’s question in this chapter is: Although every systematic discipline of knowledge studies beings, is there such a thing as a systematic discipline of knowing about being (about “being insofar as it is being,” or about “being qua being,” this latter standing as the format in which Aristotle’s wording here is most quoted)?

 

Book IV.2

            Compare this to Categories 1 (at the front of the book), and then answer this:

“Is Aristotle claiming in IV.2 that being is spoken of homonymously, synonymously, or paronymously?”

            Can you tell from the rest of IV.2 why the answer to this question would matter to Aristotle?

 

Book IV.3

            Aristotle (i) identifies the philosopher’s activity (from that of, say, the activity of the natural scientist), and (ii) discusses a principle about which he claims we can have indubitable knowledge, “the firmest principle of all.” 
            α.  What is this principle?

β.  Name another philosopher who looks for an indubitable principle.

γ.  What is the connection between (i) and (ii)?

 

Book IV. 4

Aristotle sets out to discuss how, although that “firmest principle of all” would seem to be incapable of proof (why would it seem so?), there actually are a number of refutations one can make of those who would deny this principle.  See if you can keep track of his attempted refutation.

 

Book IV. 5

            Aristotle argues against Protagorean relativism.  Recall what this is, or look it up.

 

 

Book V. 7

            It might be thought that every statement is a statement about being, in that being is spoken of in every statement.  Aristotle’s job in this chapter is defuse this objection to his view that there is a science of being qua being.  (The objection might go as, “No, Aristotle, there can’t be a systematic discipline of knowledge about what being is because every statement involves being.  There’s no moving back from it. It’s not a part of the world, and so one can’t talk of it as a specialty about which there can be a systematic understanding.”)

 

Book V.8

            In this excerpt Aristotle is describing why it might seem that substance (see the glossary’s entry for this term) is the ultimate subject (that is, a this—an enformed matter—like the bronze sphere), and also why it might seem that substance is the essence (form) of a thing (for example, sphericality).

            He does not explain why he ignores the third possibility, taken up by him elsewhere (like at De Anima 412a8) that substance might be thought of as matter. 

 

Book VII       

Book VII, also called Z, or Zeta, is generally considered the most difficult book of the Metaphysics.  University of Washington’s Professor S. Marc Cohen has an outline that might help.

 

Book VIII.1

            The review at the beginning of this chapter is divided by your editors into six numbered points, with a seventh (“We should examine...”) describing something Aristotle plans to discuss next.  The points correspond to the following sections of Aristotle:

  1. VII.1
  2. VII.2
  3. First sentence: VII.3 & 4  Second sentence: VII.13  Third sentence: VII.14
  4. VII.4-6, 12, & 15
  5. VII.10-11
  6. VII.13-14
  7. Bks. VIII & IX

 

In the rest of this chapter, Aristotle distinguishes four kinds of change, in the context of describing matter’s claim to be substance (by matter being the subject for, or what underlies, change): locomotion, growth, alternation, and coming into being and passing away.

 

Book VIII.2

            Aristotle opens this chapter by associating matter with potential.  This should sound familiar from his definition of psyche as “the first actuality of a natural body that is potentially alive” (De An. 412a27).

Aristotle then abruptly drops the discussion of actual/potential and introduces the term differentiae (diff-er-EN-shee-eye; one differentia, two differentiae).  Within the genus water, there are three species of how it can exist: ice, water, steam.  The differentiae are solidified, liquid, and vaporous.  So we define (as in 1043a9) ice as solidified water; this is a differentia + matter.  In other words, it tells us how the matter is qualified, and this quality (that is, the differentia) is what Aristotle elsewhere calls form.  So in “spherical bronze” the first word is the differentia, and indicates the form sphericality (= what it is to be a sphere).

In retrospect, Aristotle probably didn’t need to introduce this new thing, a differentia.  For he could have captured everything he wanted to say using it by using instead the notion of form.  A judgment like this, however, is easy to make with 2300 years of hindsight.  Aristotle, remember, was just feeling his way toward a system, and it wasn’t clear to him at the outset which concepts would prove the most useful.

 

Book VIII.3

            Somewhat akin to what he’d done in Categories 1 in a different context, Aristotle is warning us here about the ease of words leading one astray.  “Human,” “female,” or “oak” can refer to a specimen (that Adam, this Eve, that tree over there), and a specimen is substance in fullest sense, since it is enformed matter (= differentiated matter).  But these three terms can also refer to just the form.  When I say “A female provides the out-of-which in reproduction” I’m not talking about a specific entity the way I am when I say “A female provides the meaning of my life.  And there she is right now, so you must excuse me.”  In the former claim, I am talking not about enformed matter (that is, not about a this = not about substance in its fullest sense) but about just the form (that is, the quality of being female, or the what-it-is-to-be-female).

            Note Aristotle’s suggestion at the end of this chapter that artifacts “are not substances at all.” So all his uses of the example of a bronze sphere have to be taken as merely instructional, and not taken literally.

 

Book IX

            It is in this book that Aristotle focuses on the potential/actual distinction, although he’d mentioned it in earlier places.

            For the association between potentiality and being affected, and between actuality and doing or moving, recall (the otherwise puzzling) III.5 of the De Anima.

 

Book XII.6

            Note Aristotle’s view that motion and time cannot have come into being.  If you’re a medieval theologian reading this, then you’re dipping your quill in the red ink and marking it “This has to go.”

            Note also Aristotle’s criticism of Plato’s Forms at 1071b15 that everlasting Forms wouldn’t be able to cause changes in the perceptible world, and hence are not explanatory of the world.

            Later in that same paragraph he sets up his view that there must be something ( =  a substance) the essence of which is actuality.  It would have to be, he claims, non-material (why?) and everlasting (why?).

 

Book XII.7

            Aristotle here talks of the motion of this everlasting substance: it initiates motion (like that of the “first heaven,” whatever that is) without itself moving.  Question: how can it initiate motion if (as he said in the opening of the previous chapter) motion cannot have come into being?  [Hint: the answer has something to do with what Aristotle says in this chapter about being an object of love.  Which of the four causes would this be?]

            Starting at about 1072b19 and into XII.9, Aristotle talks of understanding.  As Fine and Irwin’s glossary indicates, the noun version of this word is nous (with noein being the verb).  If you’ve read Anaxagoras, you’ve read about nous.

 

Book XII.9

            One of Aristotle’s most famous lines is at 1074b30: the god’s understanding is an understanding of understanding.  (Or, as it’s sometimes rendered, its thinking is a thinking about thinking.)

 

Book XIII.10

            In this chapter Aristotle a puzzle to “those who say there are Ideas,” that is, the Platonists. 

            He also discusses the sense in which he (Aristotle) thinks that knowledge is of the universal.

 

 

Nicomachean Ethics

(Ta Ēthika Nikomacheia)

 

Book I

Chs. 1 & 2

Aristotle emphasizes the final cause of crafts and investigations (without calling it the final cause) and argues that some final causes are subordinate to others.  The point (final cause?!) of him doing this is to conclude at the end of I.2 that political science is the highest study concerning the human good.

Although it may strike us as strange to open a book on ethics by discussing how much more important politics is than ethics, these first two chapters turn out to serve nicely with the final chapter of NE as bookends for the ethics, indicating how Aristotle sees ethics as a necessary preface to politics.  (We have to know what the good for individuals consists in before we can discuss the good for states.)

 

Ch. 3

Aristotle lays down some methodological points, including that we should not seek more exactness in any inquiry than the topic allows and that the young are not suited for studying politics (or, by implication, ethics).  He gives two reasons about the young; what are they?

At 1098a27-b9 Aristotle makes further methodological points, including repeating some of these.

 

Ch. 4

Aristotle notes that although most (as well as “the cultivated”) think of the human good as happiness, eudaimonia (= living well = doing well), there is a range of opinions about what this consists in. 

Aristotle claims that we need to take seriously only the opinions of those who “have been brought up in fine habits.”  While this might seem to amount to Aristotle cheating by getting to ignore opinions he doesn’t agree with, consider the analogical claim: in discussing matters of health, we need not take seriously the opinions of those who have been raised in unhealthy habits, for these habits might color their ability to appreciate the healthiness of, for example, being moderate about eating sweets, being diligent about exercise, or being abstinent of tobacco.

Besides, Aristotle realizes that there still remains, even among those raised in fine habits, plenty of disagreement about what happiness consists in.

 

 

Ch. 5

Aristotle suggests that people think of happiness as whatever is the end of the life that they think is the best life.  

The end of the life of gratification is pleasure, the end of the life of politics could be either honor or virtue, and wealth is the end of the money-maker’s life. 

What are the objections Aristotle raises to the suitability of pleasure, honor, virtue, and money-making as the human good? 

Note that he defers the consideration of the life of study; this comes much later, in X.7-8.

 

Ch. 6

In this chapter Aristotle criticizes the Platonists’ conception of the Good. 

Note his use of the past tense in “those who introduced the Forms were friends of ours.  Hard to know what to make of this.  Was there a falling out?  Or is it just that Aristotle is writing this after the first-generation Platonists have died?

The second and third paragraphs in this chapter apply Aristotle’s discussion of the ten categories to the good (see Categories 4).  He thinks that there is no ONE Good, for good can be spoken of in as many ways as being can be spoken of (Metaphysics 1003a34-38 and 1028a10-13).  So there is goodness in time and goodness in amount. But not only is there no one study of goodness, there is not even one study of the opportune (= goodness in time), for the study of the opportune in war (when to attack, when to retreat, etc.) is generalship, while the study of the opportune in treating disease is medicine (when to prescribe this herb, when to prescribe surgery, when to prescribe exercise to resume, etc.).  And studying generalship does not make one a better physician; so there is no study of goodness in time, unqualified.  (Likewise with amounts, for the expert in the amount of food is what we would call a nutritionist, and in the amount of exercise, a physical trainer.)

            Aristotle gives two interesting objections to the Good (and by implication, to all Forms) in the two paragraphs 1096a35-b6.  What are they?

            By “Perhaps they are homonymous by all being derived from a single source, or by all referring to a single focus” (1096b28) Aristotle means “Perhaps they are paronymous.”  Given that he has laid paronymy out in Categories 1 as an alternative to homonymy, it is curious that he doesn’t just use the term paronymy here.  (Or might this constitute evidence that the Categories was composed after this chapter of the NE? You see the kind of supposing that reading Aristotle can encourage)

            As another objection to the Platonists, Aristotle claims that even if there is the Good, it would be irrelevant to the present inquiry.  (What’s his reasoning?)  The reply he considers on behalf of the Platonists, and his response to that reply, raise interesting points.

 

Ch. 7

Aristotle argues in I.7 that the highest human good must be both complete and self-sufficient.  Understand both claims, and see if you can find a tension between the two conditions he’s setting up for something to be considered the highest human good.

 

 

 

Ch. 8

            Happiness (see the entry for this word in Irwin and Fine’s glossary at the end of the book) is not just a state, but an activity, Aristotle claims.  He seems to think that virtuous activity is the strongest candidate for what happiness is (for it would already thereby include pleasure—why?), even though he concludes this chapter by supporting the claim that happiness also needs certain externals. 

 

A possibly inconsistent triad in NE I:  Is Aristotle inconsistent in making the following three claims?

  1. “And so the human good proves to be activity of the psyche in accord with virtue” (1098a17).
  2. “Moreover we think happiness is most choiceworthy of all goods, [since] it is not counted as one good among many” (1097b17).
  3. “And so, as we have said, happiness would seem to need this sort of prosperity added also” (1099b6).

 

Ch. 9

            The role of fortune in happiness. Note his reasoning for children and animals not being able to be happy. And what he says about Priam of Troy.

 

Ch. 10

            He considers Solon’s dictum that we should call no one happy until the person is dead. Question: what is Aristotle’s final stance on this issue?

 

Ch. 13

            An important discussion of the rational and nonrational parts of the psyche. The virtues of character (Book II) are distinguished from those of thought (Book VI).

 

Book II

Ch. 1

Aristotle makes some general remarks on virtue, which some prefer to translate “excellence.” (See the entry for “Virtue” in Irwin and Fine’s glossary, p. 355.)

 

 

Ch. 2

How virtues lie on a mean between excess and deficiency.

 

Ch. 3

Note the role Aristotle thinks pleasures and pains have in moral education.

 

Ch. 4

Be able to describe and evaluate how Aristotle tries to solve the apparent paradox of how anyone can ever come to have the virtues, since in order to be virtuous, you have to do virtuous actions, but in order to do virtuous actions, they have to come from a virtuous state of character.

 

Ch. 5

For more on what Aristotle means by “state,” see the glossary.

 

Ch. 6

Aristotle says some things that make him sound like a relativist (the mean is different for each person), yet also seems to think that actions are objectively good or bad. What gives?

Note Aristotle’s famous definition of virtue is at 1107a1: “Virtue, then, is (a) a state that decides....”

 

Ch. 7

Keep a list of the virtues, excesses and deficiencies.

 

 

Books VIII & IX on friendship

 

What and where is the textual evidence that Aristotle is an in­strumentalist about friendship (that the value of a friend consists in being an instrument by which your life is enriched) versus the evidence that he thinks that the friend must be wished well for the friend’s own sake?  Keep track of what you take to be the relevant passages.

 

VIII.1

Is Aristotle correct in saying that no amount of other goods (wealth? fame? good looks? sex? Twinkies? all of the above?) could make up for a lack of friends? Sure, his claim sounds good, but does it stand up to closer examination?  (This chapter offers something like eight different reasons for his claim.  List ’em.)

 

 

VIII.2

In saying that what is lovable is loved because it “is either good or pleasant or useful,” Aristotle is grounding his trichotomy of friendships.

He also distinguishes friendship from good will.

 

VIII.3

            What is the difference between friendships of pleasure and of utility?  Aren’t all things used used with regard to obtaining pleasure?  (Hint:  Aristotle is right; he is onto a real difference, even if the labels he uses aren’t the clearest.)

What is Aristotle’s reason for thinking that friendship of virtue is better than the other two sorts?  Jot down citations or mark relevant pas­sages. 

Is Aristotle right that there even is such a phenomenon as friendship of virtue?

 

IX.8
             Aristotle makes in this very chapter two (at least apparently) conflicting claims: (i) “Hence the good person must be a self-lover…” and (ii) “Besides, it is true that, as they say, the excellent person labors for his friends and for his native country, and will die for them if he must.”  Was Aristotle, the grandfather of the study of logic, asleep at the helm?
             (Ross’s translations of these passages are (i) “Therefore the good man should be a lover of self...” and (ii) “It is true of the good man too that he does many acts for the sake of his friends and his country....”)

Some might try to make these consistent using an approach reminiscent of the saying “Charity begins at home.” That is, perhaps Aristotle is saying that you must first love yourself before you can help others.

The trouble with this way of getting Aristotle off the hook is that Aristotle doesn’t talk of self-love as a pre-condition for acting for the sake of others. Instead, he seems to be thinking that (i) and (ii) are equally important, and so not amenable to a “primary claim, secondary claim” analysis.

A second inadequate (I think) interpretation has it that by helping friends and country, you are helping yourself. The problem with this is that it makes helping others something that would be done for one’s own sake. This second interpretation would work if Aristotle had said in (ii) “...does many acts that benefit his friends and country...,” for this wouldn’t require that the benefiting be done for their sake. (And for other passages in which Aristotle seems to endorse friendship as helping another for the other’s sake, see 1155b31, 1157b32, and 1166a3-5.)

So was Aristotle trying to have it all, thereby skating over a conceptual problem?

 

IX.9

            If happiness is the highest good because it’s complete and self-sufficient (see I.7 for what he means by these), then in what sense could a happy person need friends?

            He makes his famous claim in this chapter that your friend “is another yourself,” but it’s hard to know exactly how much to read into this.  Does he mean that metaphysically, there is no separation of identities between you and your friend?  (Probably not, because one can die while the other continues to exist.)  Does he mean that the friend is in some sense a photocopy of oneself?  Well, if so, then wouldn’t all friendship love be self-love? 

            From 1169b30 to 1170a4, your editors have inserted line numbers in order to clarify what they take to be a syllogism offered by Aristotle.  This is followed by some interesting comments Aristotle makes about us not being solitary, and earlier in this chapter (1169b19) he had held that humans are by nature political (that is, polis-dwelling). 

            Then your editors insert line numbers again for a very long stretch of reasoning, 1170a15-b8.

            From this stretch of reasoning and in the ensuing, final two paragraphs of this chapter, Aristotle seems to suggest that your friend’s existence matters to you in the same way that your own existence matters to you.  This would seem to indicate that you should value your friend intrinsically—not as an instrument to some other end.  (For in what sense could you care about your own existence as an instrument to some other end?)

 

There are two questions to be answered in Aristotle’s discussion of friendship.  First, in books VIII and IX, does Aristotle think that one engages one’s friend for the sake of oneself or for the sake of the friend?  Second, is his view correct?

 

X.6-8

            Something puzzling to many interpreters of Aristotle is how most of the Nicomachean Ethics goes on about the social virtues, but then in the final book, he starts talking about the superiority of contemplation and study.  Is he having a momentary throwback to his Platonic youth?

 

X.9

            As mentioned in these notes for NE I.1-2, this final chapter reveals how Aristotle sees the relationship between this work and that of the Politics.

 

 

Politics

(Ta Politika)

 

Book I.1

Just as with the opening of the NE, this work starts with a discussion pivoting on the final cause—in this case, the final cause of various forms of community.

In the final paragraph of this chapter, Aristotle describes his method: to analyze (literally, to break down) composite communities into their constituent communities, until he arrives at incomposite (that is, atomic, uncuttable) communities.

 

Book I.2

            Aristotle’s preference for the polis (translated here as “city,” but meaning more like “city and surrounding provinces” or even our “greater metropolitan area”) is clear.  Foreigners (barbaroi, because Greeks thought non-Greeks sounded like they were saying “bar bar bar,” akin to our “blah, blah, blah”) are all slavish, he thinks.

            An important view for Aristotle is that “the city exists by nature,” for he is therefore saying that the polis exist by phusis, not by nomos—by nature, not by convention.  So it is not the result of a social contract or tricked up merely in order to allow us to satisfy our conventional wants.  We are as much polis-dwelling as bees are hive-dwelling.  A solitary person has an incompletely developed nature.

            When he says at 1253a20 that “the whole is necessarily prior to the part,” he does not mean prior in time (for how could the whole come into being unless the parts came first?).  He means logical priority, not temporal priority.  That is, the entire animal is logically prior to the foot of the animal, insofar as the foot is the foot of the (whole) animal.  So the notion of the whole is needed in giving an account (or definition, or statement of the essence of) the part. 

 

Book II.1

            Can you detect Aristotle’s empiricism at work in this paragraph, as opposed to how Plato went about laying out his description of the best political community?

 

Book II.2-5

            Aristotle lays out an extended discussion against Plato’s recommendation in the Republic to get rid of private property (though Plato recommends this only for the guardians) and to get rid of private family relations (the private family having been said by Aristotle at 1252b10 to be the atom out of which the polis is built). 

Oddly, Aristotle refers to Socrates as the proponent of these ideas; surely he means Socrates the character in the Republic, not the historical Socrates.  Does his not mentioning Plato by name indicate bad blood between the two of them?  Or perhaps it was simply a matter of accuracy; that is, maybe Plato never believed in the Republic, and he’d written it only as a discussion starter for his students.  You see the kind of hints we’re left to squeeze lemonade out of sometimes.

 

Book III.1-12

            In this book, Aristotle shows what system of political organization he believes in.  In III.1 we see how he defines citizenship not in terms of location (where you live or where you were born), but in terms of activity: in particular, one who shares in judging and ruling.  Biennial voting wouldn’t cut it for Aristotle, even with occasional jury duty. 

            In III.4 we see how, in the spirit of emphasizing experience, he claims that ruling well requires having been ruled. 

            In III.9 Aristotle makes the claim that the polis does not exist for the sake of (there’s the final cause again!) allowing people to acquire property, for the sake of even just living, or for the sake of forming alliances for defense or trade.  Rather the end is living well for its parts, and you will recall the lesson from the Nicomachean Ethics: excellence (virtue) is necessary (even if not sufficient) for living well (= happiness; see NE I.4).

            In III.11 Aristotle takes up the central issue on which his political theory differs from Plato’s: should the masses or the experts rule?  See if you can put into your own words his final answer, with any qualifications he gives.

            Section III.12 contains Aristotle’s discussion of justice, or fairness.  He is not an egalitarian, but is arguing for a meritocracy.  His discussion of allocating flutes is revealing and fascinating for its time, for he is saying that the better flutes should go to the better flutist, even if the better flutist is better by a smaller amount than he is uglier and worse born than the other.

 

Book VII

            Chapter 1 sounds like a recap of the parts of the Nicomachean Ethics that are most relevant for Aristotle’s discussion in Chapter 2 of the goal of the best political system.

            Chapters 13 and 15 show themselves to be presupposing the Nicomachean Ethics.  The three conditions given in chapter 13 as requirements for becoming good certainly fit with the NE, but are more crisply stated here than in the NE.

 

 

Poetics

(Peri Poiētikēs, About Poetics)

 

Irwin and Fine’s footnote 2 is very important, and gives some sense of the directions in which interpreters have gone with this passage.  Note that, as indicated in footnote 1, Aristotle’s word for purification is katharsis.  Freud and other early psychoanalytic theorists were much taken with this passage in Aristotle.  

In ch. 13, we get more details on Aristotle’s views on the role of fear and pity.  Interesting to note is how he thinks watching tragedy (and so reading tragic novels and watching tragic movies, even though those media didn’t exist in his day) performs a kind of therapy on the psyche.  Art is thus not morally neutral, but is good for us. 

Aristotle reveals himself to be something of a purist when it comes to keeping tragedy and comedy distinct.  He realizes that popular sentiment wants a happy ending, but he shows that what he thinks most true to the art form of tragedy is bad things happening to good people through some error they make (but probably not character fault of theirs).  The audience always likes it when bad people get their comeuppance, but insofar as this is a happy ending, it belongs in a comedy.  For happy endings do not get us purification from/of pity or fear.

 

 

Materials supplementary to Irwin & Fine

(Readings I have circulated to my students)

 

Law I-V

Notice how Aristotle, ever the biologist, likens learning to the growing of a plant. (Is his use of learning medicine as his example of learning perhaps related to his daddy having been the court physician to Amyntas III, emperor of Macedon?)

The closing comments on scientific training requiring a religious-like initiation are more suggestive than clear.

 

Rhetoric II.xii-xiv

            Aristotle discusses the typical character of the young, of the old, and of those in the prime of life. If this is reminiscent of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, perhaps this is not surprising.

            Lesson: beware the professor who is older than 49!

 

Politics I.3-6

            These chapters contain Aristotle’s famous discussion of slavery, which he divides into two sorts: those who are slaves by nature (phusis) and those who are slaves by convention (nomos). Not surprisingly, he comes out in favor of natural slavery, and against slavery by convention.

Interestingly, most slavery in the ancient Mediterranean (Egyptian, Greek, Etruscan, Macedonian, and Roman) was slavery by convention—that is, the sources of most slaves were military conquests (typically, adult males on the losing side were killed, and women and children were taken as slaves) and piracy (pirates raiding passenger ships or raiding seaside villages for captives to sell on the slave market). Neither of these means of entry into slavery would pass Aristotle’s test.

 

Politics IV.11

Aristotle here discusses what he takes to be the realistically best polis. As in the Rhetoric passage above, note the echoes of his doctrine of the mean.

 

Politics VII.9

            Aristotle’s discussion here of the best polis contrasts with what he had said in the previous excerpt. Did Aristotle not notice this?

            Perhaps these two passages are addressing different questions: what’s the realistically best polis vs. what’s the idealistically best polis?

            Where do you see overlap with, and divergence from, Plato’s kallipolis?

 

Politics VIII.1-3        

            In VIII.1 Aristotle argues for education being publicly provided and publicly funded.  Note that his argument is not that the poor need help paying for education, but simply that education is so crucial to the health of the polis that the polis is responsible for providing education.   Education is political, he is saying.  Not in the sense that education is politically biased (like toward the right or toward the left), but in the sense that it is a duty of political associations, like building roads is.

            In VIII.2-3 Aristotle argues that education should not be limited to what is useful, but should aim at “leisured activity” (not an oxymoron, if you get Aristotle; he is not talking about reclining on a beach).  Some education should be “noble and suitable for a free person,” and Aristotle’s closing line to chapter 3 is one of his few memorable lines. 

            Putting these chapters together, we have that education should be public and should be (at least in large part) liberal arts.